Translate this page:
Please select your language to translate the article


You can just close the window to don't translate
Library
Your profile

Back to contents

Philosophy and Culture
Reference:

Analytical philosophy of law in the civil litigation: how to perform actions using words

Shliakhtin Nikita Dmitrievich

Leading specialist; Legal Protection Department; PJSC 'MOEK'

119311, Russia, Moscow, Stroiteley str., 6, room 3, sq. 23

nik.shliakhtin@yandex.ru

DOI:

10.7256/2454-0757.2025.4.73318

EDN:

ATWWNS

Received:

10-02-2025


Published:

04-05-2025


Abstract: The subject of the study is the judicial process of the Russian Federation. The author considers the judicial procedure as a communicative model functioning according to the principles of request-response. Within the communicative model, there are certain rules of context, as well as rules for the performance of actions by the parties and their direct representatives. Such actions are carried out by the parties using words that have a certain form and are reflected in the case file. The analysis of speech acts, both written and oral, allowed the author to name individual legal facts according to the classification proposed by G.L.A. Hart. Speech acts used for philological analysis are a ubiquitous form of action in one's own interests or in the interests of the principal in the judicial process. The application of the communicative theory of law made it possible to find a method for changing the dynamics of the judicial process. The methodology of the work is a philological analysis of speech acts used by the parties in the judicial process, as well as a comparison of the result of the speech act with the material trace reflected in the procedural documents of the court case. The result of the work is a confirmation of the predominance of the principle of oral judicial process over the principle of writing, which is expressed in the special position of the audio protocol as a trace of procedural actions using words. The field of application of the research results is the judicial system of the Russian Federation, as a communicative system of requests and responses to conflict resolution. The novelty of the research is expressed in the application of philological and philosophical analysis to the communicative dispute resolution system, which allows us to conclude that the parties directly influence the judge during the trial and change the dynamics of the trial by performing actions using words. The author comes to the conclusion that each of the certain types of speech effects will be an independent legal fact, and the necessary form of their fixation is audio recording of the court session.


Keywords:

Civil procedure, arbitration procedure, communicative theory of law, analytical philosophy of law, philosophy of language, speech act, procedural legal facts, descriptive concepts, ascriptive concepts, illocutionary force

This article is automatically translated.

The civil procedure is based on a combination of written and oral proceedings in the case. These principles receive independent consolidation only after the adoption of the Statute of Civil Procedure in 1864. In its modern form, the principle of verbality is enshrined in article 157 of the Civil Procedure Code of the Russian Federation, with a more detailed statement in the wording of article 81 of the Arbitration Procedure Code of the Russian Federation on the possibility of a party to submit to the arbitration court its explanations about circumstances known to it that are relevant to the case, in writing or orally.

Ovcharenko A.V. pointed out that in the civil process, these principles are revealed in two independent elements, namely in the form of the process itself and in the system of rules of evidence. [1, p. 13] The process is by its nature a complex procedural fact with a consistent accumulation of elements. [2, p. 224] The rules of evidence aim to establish acceptable methods of persuasion. The proof is carried out before the court, with the aim of confirming the right in a binding act of authority. [3, p. 34] An authoritative binding act, in turn, is the last element of a complex procedural fact.

The main difficulty of this study is, as Ludwig Wittgenstein correctly noted, the inability to express through language what expresses itself in language. [4, p. 76] Thus, the research methodology is more intuitive and scientific, aiming to expand the discourse around the communicative theory of law in relation to the civil process, rather than to give a specific conclusion about how legal actions are performed through words. At the same time, a certain result has been achieved not only through linguistic analysis of law, but also through semantic analysis of the actions that we perform with the help of words, including during the judicial process.

The fundamental basis of the research is the protocol of the court session, which records the trace of the mechanism that analytical philosophy calls "actions with words." It is particularly interesting that in no other way, except through such a mechanism, it is impossible to imagine the dynamics of the judicial process. In the process of forming a separate procedural fact, the will of the person involved in the case is imprinted on the materials of the case, which is especially important for the subsequent historical analysis of the motives of the persons and the circumstances in which they acted.

A classic example of the classification of types of legal facts is the system proposed by O.A. Krasavchikov. The classification is based on the volitional criterion. All legal facts, depending on the presence of will in them, fall into two main groups: legal events and legal actions. [5, P. 82]

With regard to the civil procedure, E.V. Vaskovsky and E.G. Lukyanov express the opinion that a procedural action by itself cannot form a procedural legal fact. Only the actual composition is possible, in particular, the procedural action and the procedural response of the court to such an action will form a procedural fact. P.F. Eliseikin believes that not just the court's response to the action, but the court's authorization (approval) of the procedural action of the party leads to the appearance of a procedural legal fact. [6, P. 48]

From P.F. Eliseikin's thesis, it can be concluded that all procedural facts should be reflected in court documents – protocols, definitions and decisions.

Based on a brief introduction to the theory of procedural legal facts as a theoretical model, it would be wise to proceed to the consideration of the practical side of the process, namely, the question of how exactly procedural legal facts change the dynamics of the process. At first glance, it may seem that in order to answer this question, it is necessary to refer to the transcript of the trial and correlate the will of the judge in terms of judicial guidance of a particular process with the procedural documents of the parties and the court. Of course, this is the most obvious way, which nevertheless requires some depth of study of the issue.

As we said above, a procedural legal fact is exposed in the form of court rulings, but the reason for the court's conclusion that the process needs to be moved to the next stage (further, it is not necessary to talk about the stages of the trial set out in the procedural codes, for example, the definition of conducting a forensic examination also fits the criteria we set) is in accordance with The principles of competitiveness and dispositivity are either the expression of the will of the persons involved in the case, or a procedural legal fact with the subsequent accumulation of elements – in other words, when the very meaning of the process leads the judge to make a certain decision, for example, to end the stage of examining evidence and proceed to the debate of the parties.

Thus, the expression of will can be oral or written, however, according to the requirements of the procedural codes, it must take the form of a petition or a procedural document containing the position of the party on a particular issue.

The petition expresses a specific expression of will concerning the purely procedural part of the party to the trial, while the procedural document containing the position of the party in its petitioning part expresses the will to resolve the material issue, although in the most general terms it may act as a prerequisite for the application of the petition.

The petition or the position of the party expressed in the procedural document always has the form of a request, which must be answered by the court. As the court issues a ruling on the resolution of the petition, so the analysis of the party's position must be present in the court decision – the court cannot ignore the arguments of the persons involved in the case. The only exception is the custom, which is not fixed in the procedural code – the opportunity to leave the issue of consideration of the petition open. This dexterity of the court can give the judge time to make the right decision regarding the petition, especially in a situation where not all the circumstances of the case are known. However, in the end, the judge must allow the petition.

The situation when the request has no form, but is caused by the "necessity of the process", leaves more room for discussion. We can say that there is no request at all in this case, since there is no addressee. Consequently, communication at this stage is one–sided - from the court to the parties, in an imperative form. The "necessity of the process" is the last element of a legal structure with a consistent accumulation of elements, in which the list of elements remains open. The judge himself makes a decision based on his own conviction about the correctness of the conduct of the process when considering a particular case.

As is often the case in situations of interpersonal interaction, a judge can resolve a request from a person involved in the case based not only on a rational approach, but also on an emotional one. It is very difficult to predict the judge's reaction to the request, as it is quite rare for the parties to agree on the next stage of the process. The addressee must accurately determine the place and meaning of the message to the court in order to achieve a result.

Since most petitions are filed in the middle of the process, the judge does not have time to familiarize himself with the procedural document, and he will make a decision based on the situation. Nevertheless, this does not mean that the request should not leave a mark on paper – this is the duty of the party, and it is in its interests to provide the court with a document so that in the future this procedural legal fact can be reflected in the court decision.

The logic of the trial is structured in such a way that at the beginning of each court session, the judge asks about the need to resolve the petitions of the parties that impede the consideration of the case. Therefore, together with a short request for judicial guidance, the party must state the reasons and circumstances that served as the basis for the application. In this regard, a "pool" of documents will be very advantageous, which, although they have different grounds (for example, a petition and a response to a claim), will nevertheless be connected by a single semantic line. The party must convince the court that this is exactly what the next stage of the trial should be. It can be said that the legal fact, which is a document, is a draft court decision in terms of judicial guidance.

As in the classical theory of argumentation, the request to the court is best presented in the form:

1. Thesis (a statement whose truth or acceptability needs to be substantiated);

2. Argumentation (statements that are used as arguments to reach agreement with the proposed point of view);

3. Demonstrations (a way of connecting arguments and a proven thesis). [7, p. 27]

The eloquence of the addressee is of particular importance – oratory is highly appreciated among judicial lawyers, since all types of processes, with the exception of simplified proceedings, have an oral presentation.

There is a section in the theory of philosophy of language developed by L. Wittgenstein, J. Austin, J. Searle and G.L.A. Hart in the middle and end of the last century. L. Wittgenstein noticed in his early works that words, in particular names, denote the real things of the world around us. These names cannot be destroyed, even if the object that was in the real world has ceased to exist. For example, we know that there is a flower growing in our room, we can call it "flower", we can call it "Vitaly Flower", but if it dies, then a specific flower or "Vitaly Flower" will still remain in the world of words, thoughts and images. Thus, L. Wittgenstein concluded, "objects form the substance of the world," and the substance itself "is something that exists regardless of what takes place." [8, pp. 2.021, 2.024.]

Later, for legal discourse, G.L.A. Hart will call words that denote an object of the real world, for example, a flower, descriptive, and words that are not "tied" to the physical world of being, non-descriptive (ascretive). For example, a flower is a descriptive concept, and conscientiousness is an ascriptive one. V.V. Oglenzev, in his research work on the analytical philosophy of law, writes the following about non-descriptive (ascreptive) concepts: "therefore, a non-descriptive term should be understood not as a term that does not mean anything, but as a term using a non-standard type of designation in relation to the usual and the generally accepted way of defining the semantics of words. The usual, that is, descriptive, or, in a narrower sense, empirical term assumes a semantic connection between the term and the object to which it refers, in the form of an "ocular", "mirror" or "pictorial" metaphor. The term describes, reflects, and forms a mental image of the object or process it is talking about." [9, P. 126]

Thus, from the point of view of the philosophy of language, there is a justification for dividing legal facts into the material facts themselves (events or phenomena with which the rule of law connects the appearance, change or termination of a material legal relationship) and circumstances relevant to the case, with which the rule of law, although it connects the dynamics of a material legal relationship, nevertheless such circumstances have only a mental image of an object or process that cannot be recorded anywhere for subsequent use in civil and arbitration proceedings. Examples of circumstances relevant to the case are good faith, deception, a flawed expert opinion, an object that poses a threat to the life and health of citizens, etc.

G.L.A. Hart, who, following I. Bentham, questions the effectiveness of using the traditional method of definition by means of per genus et diferentiam of such legal concepts as "objective law", "subjective law", "responsibility", "state", etc. Despite the well-known common usage of these words, it is unclear because, in comparison with most common words, these legal terms are considered "anomalous" in various respects. Attempts to define these terms show that they do not have a direct connection with their factual counterparts, which most ordinary words have, for which we refer to this connection. [10, pp. 535-558]

It should be borne in mind that language as a form of communication is a means of communication and is possible only in human society. At the same time, the terms, structure and form used in jurisprudence make it possible to classify legal language into a special category, since each word in legal discourse has a strong connection with either a material or a procedural fact. It can be said that the legal language was created in order to describe events and phenomena as accurately as possible, without giving them any emotional coloring. In this way, legal language causes both boredom and respect, but law, as the art of kindness and justice ("Jus est ars boni et aequi" – the ancient Roman jurist Celsus), does not have the ability to make decisions through emotions. Nevertheless, it is possible to make decisions and act through words.

If we return to the civil procedure, we should pay attention to the change in procedural status through precisely described in practice, almost sacred expressions. "We file a motion to involve A as a co-defendant," "The Court, by its ruling, appoints an expert examination in the expert organization B," "The court proceeds to examine the evidence."

In the minutes of the court session, each such wording will mean an independent procedural legal fact that has changed the dynamics of the process in one direction or another. A competent trial lawyer always has a strategy for conducting a case, which he strives to implement in a court session. The strategy has the form of expression of procedural documents and an oral report to the court through the implementation of the principle of dispositivity. The commission or non-performance of any procedural actions is the responsibility of the party. By establishing procedural rules, the Civil Procedure Code and the Arbitration Procedure Code create a context within which the parties' speech is interpreted. It is difficult to imagine a situation when, when buying ice cream at a stall, a boy would tell the seller: "I submit a petition to impose the costs of buying ice cream on my father." Nevertheless, the phrase about assigning the costs of conducting a forensic examination to a party is understood by lawyers as the simplest and most obvious phrase during the process.

Thus, "any rule is based on the idea of obeying or following it." [11, p. 84]. G.L.A. Hart criticized the model of coercive orders of the sovereign, pointing out the need for a "recognition rule", according to which "wherever such a recognition rule is adopted, both private and official persons receive a reliable criterion for identifying the primary rules of duty" [12, P. 63]. As stated in the previous paragraphs, the right of recognition is a communication between the state and citizens, through which the law is legitimized.

Nevertheless, G.L.A. Hart distinguishes between a situation of an "order" from the state through the issuance of a law and a situation when an order is given by a robber. G.L.A. Hart describes a situation with a robber who, at the threat of his life, orders a citizen to hand over a bag to him, noting that "ordering people to do certain things is a form of communication, and it really involves "addressing" them, that is, attracting their attention or taking steps to attract it, but passing laws for people does not do that." Further, the scientist writes: "What is usually meant by those who say that laws are "addressed" to certain persons is that there are persons to whom a particular law applies, that is, from whom it requires to behave in a certain way. If we use the word "converted" here, we may not be able to notice the important difference between passing a law and issuing a personal order, and we may also confuse two different questions: "To whom does this law apply?" and "To whom was it announced?" [13, pp. 15-16]

In our opinion, this contradiction is eliminated by Federal Law No. 5-FZ of June 14, 1994."On the Procedure for the Publication and Entry into Force of Federal Constitutional Laws, Federal Laws, and Acts of the Chambers of the Federal Assembly" with the obligation to publish federal constitutional laws, federal laws, and acts of the Chambers of the Federal Assembly with their subsequent entry into force ten days after the date of their official publication, unless the laws or acts of the Chambers themselves establish a different procedure for entry their power.

Another aspect of G.L.A. Hart's reflections is important for us, in particular, that the robber's order does not contain a "recognition rule" on the part of society, such an order is condemned, as it violates the property right of the person who owns the bag, and also potentially poses a threat to the life and health of a citizen. In turn, laws are legitimate to the extent that they are recognized by society as socially justified limitations of the individual.

By creating rules for communication in court, the law also establishes the context, taking into account the specifics of each specific case. It would be at least unwise in cases of torts to report to the court about unjustified enrichment, therefore, the context in the most general form can be called: 1) procedural rules; 2) the subject and the basis of the claim.

J. Searle notes that "some rules regulate the forms of behavior that existed before them, for example, the rules of etiquette regulate interpersonal relationships, but these relationships exist independently of the rules of etiquette. Other rules do not just regulate, but create and define new forms of behavior. Football rules, for example, do not just regulate the game of football, but, so to speak, create the very possibility of such activity or define it." [14, p. 58]

This idea was subsequently developed by G.L.A. Hart, citing the example of the game of chess, stating that for children who do not know the rules of the game of chess, such a game will seem like just an arbitrary movement of pieces on a chessboard. Thus, a child who arbitrarily moves a piece does not actually make a move.

Next, we will try to figure out how the parties make their "move" in the lawsuit.

J. Searle focused his attention on the meaning of the speech act. The speech act itself consists of three levels:

  1. An illocutionary act is an action that we perform by uttering a certain phrase (we can convince someone, ask, accuse, instruct);
  2. A locative act is the act of pronouncing certain sounds or writing down certain icons on paper.;
  3. A perlocative act is the effect of our utterance on the actions, thoughts, or emotions of listeners (our utterance may or may not convince the interlocutor, force him to do something, cause him irritation or boredom, etc.). [15, p. 79]

Thus, an illocutionary act is an intention to achieve a result that can be represented in the formula "X is considered Y". Thus, by submitting a request for an expert examination, we mean "let the court consider this request as the basis for the transition of the trial to the stage of expert examination." By filing a petition, the party is trying to influence the addressee of the speech act – the court.

Next, J. Searle points to the necessary part of the illocutionary act, the convention or "condition of sincerity." The essence lies in the absence of an internal and external contradiction between what a person thinks and what a person declares to the addressee. You can't say, "I'm applying for an expert examination, but I lied."

In addition to context and sincerity, another part of the illocutionary act is needed – the form. Law as a science, art, and craft is very formalized and requires that the right words be spoken at the right time and in the right place. In particular, leaving the deliberation room, the judge begins to announce the decision on the case with the words "the decision on the case is announced in the name of the Russian Federation ...", without which the decision will not be valid, at the same time skipping the stage of explaining the rights to the parties before the start of the trial in the form prescribed by the procedural code will be a violation of the procedure for holding a court session and in In some particularly sensitive cases, this is the basis for revoking a court decision (article 165 of the Code of Civil Procedure of the Russian Federation). According to paragraph 2 of Article 154 of the Arbitration Procedure Code of the Russian Federation, the persons participating in the case and other participants in the arbitration process address the arbitration court with the words: "Dear court!". They give their explanations and testimony to the court, questions to other persons involved in the case, and answers to questions standing up. A deviation from this rule may be allowed only with the permission of the court.

J. Searle distinguished the following classes of illocutionary speech acts:

  • Representations – place the responsibility on the addressee for the truth of the speech act (for example, an oath);
  • Directives are directed at the addressee in order to encourage the latter to do something (for example, to ask);
  • Commissioners – impose responsibility on the addressee to follow a certain line of conduct (for example, "we will request a postponement of the court session to familiarize ourselves with the defendant's position");
  • Expressive – describe the psychological attitude of the addressee to the addressee (for example, to thank);
  • Declarations – a speech act establishes the state of affairs (for example, "to satisfy claims–).

In civil and arbitration proceedings, an example of a representative would be an expert's signature on criminal liability for perjury, a directive would be a party's petition, an italicized statement would be the party's expressed intention to follow a line of conduct, an expressive greeting from the judge and his secretary, or gratitude to the court before being removed from the courtroom, a declaration would be any decision. courts on a specific issue.

In turn, J. Austin identifies the following five groups of verbs according to their illocutionary force:

  • Verdicts are the implementation of a value judgment (for example, "we recognize the claims in part ...", "the expert evaluates the damage in the amount of ...");
  • Excersivity – the manifestation of influence or the exercise of power (for example, "the amount of damage is confirmed by an expert opinion");
  • Commission – making a commitment or a statement of intent (for example, signing an expert's statement of responsibility for giving false testimony);
  • Behaviors – an expression of an attitude (for example, "we do not trust the testimony of a witness due to our interest in the outcome of the case");
  • Expositions are explanations of the grounds, arguments, and messages (for example, "a decision is lawful if it is made in strict compliance with the rules of procedural law and in full compliance with the rules of substantive law that are applicable to this legal relationship, or based on the application, if necessary, of an analogy of law or analogy of law"). [16, P. 120]

Another important aspect that G.L.A. Hart drew attention to is the repealability of legal concepts. For example, we declare that the ownership of the car belongs to A. This speech act is a statement of fact. Nevertheless, confirmed by proper evidence, this statement about the fact will move into the field of law, and then it will already be a statement about the law. If the evidence of A's ownership of the car is not presented to the court or is refuted by the other party, then the "cancellation" of the statement will occur – the court recognizes the ownership of the car for person B.

The given example of a car is an example of a constative (statement), according to J. Austin. In turn, the dynamics of the civil process occurs through performances that cannot be "canceled." "When uttering a perfomative utterance, we always perform some act, or, equivalently, perform some action that, apparently, we could hardly have performed in any other way, at least with the same accuracy." [17, p. 23]

Thus, procedural legal facts arise through perfomatives, the distinctive features of which we have described above. Let's remember them:

the context of the judicial process, consisting of procedural rules, the subject and the basis of the claim;

the condition of the addressee's sincerity;

the power or authority of the addressee to change the procedural legal relationship;

perfomatives, as applied to civil and arbitration proceedings, cannot be "canceled".

One more important and final quality of performances in the civil process should be considered, which follows from the "irrevocability" of this speech act. A classic example of performance art is given in the literature: the captain of a ship breaks a bottle of champagne on the deck and announces "I name you Streaky!" The conditions of context, sincerity, and authority have been met. Nevertheless, A.A. Melnikov drew attention to the following circumstance: "if a person with champagne called a ship by one name (for example, he made a slip of the tongue, joked or made an indistinct sound), and it went by another name in the documents, this will not change how the ship is recorded in the documents. That is, the statement of the guy with the champagne does not contain a universally valid naming of the ship, the connection between the statement and the naming is ultimately accidental." [18, p. 299]

Let's consider this situation in relation to the judicial process – how did the legislator ensure the responsibility of a person or his representative for "actions through words"?

First of all, we should address the importance of an audio protocol in the process. This technology allows you to accurately correlate the actions that occurred during the court session with the consequences that they produced.

According to article 155 of the Arbitration Procedure Code of the Russian Federation, during each court session of the arbitration court of the first instance, as well as when performing certain procedural actions outside the court session, recording is conducted using audio recording means and a written protocol is drawn up. At the same time, it is important to note the priority of the audio protocol, since the written protocol is an additional means of recording process data, including oral statements, petitions of persons involved in the case, consultations of specialists, agreements of the parties on the factual circumstances of the case, stated requirements and objections.

A similar regulation is established in Chapter 21 of the Code of Civil Procedure of the Russian Federation, with the exception of the priority of the audio protocol. Thus, the problem posed by Melnikov A.A. is solved by perceiving the speech of the parties during the court session through subsequent listening to an audio protocol.

Summarizing the results of this study, it should be noted that the types of speech acts used in the course of communication are possible only if a certain context and ritual are observed. Communication itself is the operation of images of objects using descriptive and non-descriptive concepts. But since communication itself is inherently "virtual," it doesn't matter what concepts (descriptive or non-descriptive) the person involved in the case uses during the court session. The figurative field itself, in which information is transmitted through speech acts, is possible only under the conditions of the choice of the person carrying out the communication. We can say that the law as such is secondary to the variability of events, however, using the example of the judicial process, we have shown how the potential variability of events becomes a judicial reality through actions with the help of words. It should be borne in mind that words are a reflection of a thought that has meaning, and it is at the moment of formation of a thought loaded with meaning that a person's personal right to express it is formed through a speech act, which, in turn, leads to a change in reality according to such a thought.

References
1. Ovcharenko, A. V. (2013). Combination of the principles of orality and writtenness in civil and arbitration procedures: Author's abstract of the dissertation for the degree of candidate of legal sciences (12.00.15). Saratov State Law Academy.
2. Shlyakhtin, N. D. (2024). On the content of procedural legal relations in the context of the communicative approach. Education and Law, 11, 224. https://doi.org/10.24412/2076-1503-2024-11-222-226
3. Amosov, S. M. (2004). Judicial cognition in the arbitration process: Author's abstract of the dissertation for the degree of candidate of legal sciences (12.00.15).
4. Wittgenstein, L. (2005). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. In L. Wittgenstein, Selected Works (pp. 76). Publishing House "Territory of the Future".
5. Krasavchikov, O. A. (1958). Legal facts in civil law.
6. Eliseikin, P. F. (1974). Subject and principles of Soviet civil procedural law.
7. Tulchinsky, G. L. (2016). Logic and theory of argumentation: A textbook for academic bachelor's degree.
8. Wittgenstein, L. (2005). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. In L. Wittgenstein, Selected Works (p. 38).
9. Ogleznev, V. V. (2012). H. L. A. Hart and the formation of analytical philosophy of law.
10. Simpson, A. W. B. (1965). The analysis of legal concepts. Law Quarterly Review, 80, 535-558.
11. Ogleznev, V. V. (2012). H. L. A. Hart and the formation of analytical philosophy of law.
12. Hart, H. L. A. (2007). The concept of law.
13. Hart, H. L. A. (2007). The concept of law.
14Philosophy of language (J. R. Searle, Ed.). (2010).
15. Ryabinskaya, N. S. (2002). Speech as a social action: Basic concepts of discourse analysis. Sociological Journal, 4, 79.
16. Austin, J. L. (1999). How to do things with words. In J. L. Austin, Selected Works (p. 120).
17Philosophy of language (J. R. Searle, Ed.). (2010).
18. Melnikov, A. A. (2022). On the applicability of speech act theory in discussions about freedom of speech: Some examples from John Austin. Philosophy. Journal of the Higher School of Economics, 6(3), 299. https://doi.org/10.17323/2587-8719-2022-3-289-312

First Peer Review

Peer reviewers' evaluations remain confidential and are not disclosed to the public. Only external reviews, authorized for publication by the article's author(s), are made public. Typically, these final reviews are conducted after the manuscript's revision. Adhering to our double-blind review policy, the reviewer's identity is kept confidential.
The list of publisher reviewers can be found here.

The subject of the research in the article submitted for review is, as its name implies, the analytical philosophy of law in the civil process. The declared boundaries of the study have been observed by the scientist. The research methodology is not disclosed in the text of the article. The relevance of the research topic chosen by the author is not substantiated. Additionally, the scientist needs to list the names of the leading experts involved in the research of the issues raised in the article, as well as disclose the degree of their study. The scientific novelty of the work is manifested in a number of conclusions of the author: "Thus, from the point of view of the philosophy of language, there is a justification for dividing legal facts into the material facts themselves (events or phenomena with which the rule of law relates the appearance, change or termination of a material legal relationship) and circumstances relevant to the case, with which the rule of law Nevertheless, such circumstances have only a mental image of the subject or process, which cannot be recorded anywhere for subsequent use in civil and arbitration proceedings. Examples of circumstances relevant to the case are good faith, deception, a flawed expert opinion, an object that poses a threat to the life and health of citizens, etc."; "Thus, procedural legal facts arise through performances, the distinctive features of which we cited above. Let us recall them: 1. the context of the judicial process, consisting of procedural norms and the subject and basis of the claim; 2. the condition of the addressee's sincerity; 3. the addressee's authority or authority to change the procedural legal relationship; 4. perfomatives, in relation to civil and arbitration proceedings, cannot be "canceled", etc. Thus, the article makes a definite contribution to the development of Russian legal science and certainly deserves the attention of potential readers. The scientific style of the research is fully supported by the author. The structure of the work is not entirely logical. The introductory part of the article is missing. In the main part of the work, the author substantiates the application of the analytical philosophy of law in the civil process, finding out how procedural legal facts change the dynamics of the process. The final part of the article is missing. The content of the article corresponds to its title, but it is not without its formal drawbacks. So, the author writes: "With regard to the civil process, E.V. Vaskovsky and E.G. Lukyanov express the opinion that the procedural action by itself cannot form a procedural legal fact" - "With regard to the civil process, E.V. Vaskovsky and E.G. Lukyanov express the opinion that the procedural action by itself cannot form a procedural legal fact" (see for punctuation). The scientist notes: "Based on a brief introduction to the theory of procedural legal facts as a theoretical model, it would be reasonable to move on to the consideration of the practical side of the process, namely, the question of how exactly procedural legal facts change the dynamics of the process" - "Based on a brief introduction to the theory of procedural legal facts as a theoretical model, it would be reasonable to proceed to the consideration of the practical side of the process, namely, to the question of exactly how procedural legal facts change the dynamics of the process" (see for the agreement of words). The author indicates: "Thus, the expression of will can be oral or written, but according to the requirements of the procedural codes it must take the form of a petition or a procedural document containing the position of the party on a certain issue" - "Thus, the expression of will can be oral or written, but according to the requirements of the procedural codes it must take the form of a petition or a procedural document containing the position of the party regarding a specific issue" (see for punctuation and stylistics). Thus, the article needs additional proofreading - it contains typos, spelling, punctuation and stylistic errors (the list of typos and errors given in the review is not exhaustive!). The initials of the scientist in the text of the article are placed before his last name. The bibliography of the study is presented by 11 sources (monographs, scientific articles, textbook), including in English. From a formal point of view, this is enough. There is an appeal to the opponents, both general and private (E.V. Vaskovsky, E.G. Lukyanov, etc.), and it is quite sufficient. The scientific discussion is conducted correctly by the author. The provisions of the work are properly reasoned and illustrated with examples. There are no conclusions based on the results of the study. The interest of the readership in the article submitted for review can be shown primarily by experts in the field of philosophy of law, theory of state and law, civil procedure, arbitration, provided that it is finalized: disclosure of the research methodology, substantiation of the relevance of its topic, clarification of the structure of the work, formulation of clear and specific conclusions based on the results of the research, elimination of violations in the design of the article.

Second Peer Review

Peer reviewers' evaluations remain confidential and are not disclosed to the public. Only external reviews, authorized for publication by the article's author(s), are made public. Typically, these final reviews are conducted after the manuscript's revision. Adhering to our double-blind review policy, the reviewer's identity is kept confidential.
The list of publisher reviewers can be found here.

A scientific article on the topic "Analytical philosophy of law in the civil process" is submitted for review.: how to perform actions using words" for publication in the journal Philosophy and Culture. The article is devoted to the analysis of the role of speech acts in the civil process from the standpoint of the analytical philosophy of law. The author explores how words and linguistic constructions influence the dynamics of judicial proceedings, the formation of procedural facts and decision-making. Special attention is paid to the connection between linguistic theories (L. Wittgenstein, J. Austin, J. Searle, G.L.A. Hart) and the practice of judicial proceedings. The research combines the methods of: linguistic analysis - the study of speech acts (illocutionary, performative) and their role in law; comparative legal analysis - a comparison of the norms of the CPC and the APC of the Russian Federation; theoretical and philosophical approach - interpretation of legal facts through the prism of the philosophy of language; practical analysis - analysis of examples from judicial practice (protocols, petitions). The methodology is interdisciplinary in nature, which allowed the author to reveal the topic comprehensively. The topic of the article is relevant due to the growing interest in the communicative aspects of law in the context of the digitalization of legal proceedings, the need for a clear understanding of linguistic constructions to minimize judicial errors, and the development of theories of speech acts in jurisprudence, especially in the context of procedural codes. The work fills the gap between abstract philosophical concepts and their practical application in law. The novelty is manifested in the following aspects. The author synthesizes the ideas of the analytical philosophy of law and the civil process. The author's classification of speech acts in legal proceedings has been carried out (using examples of petitions and court decisions). The analysis of "non-descriptive" legal concepts (good faith, threat to life) is carried out through the prism of the philosophy of language. Practical conclusions are drawn about the importance of audio protocols for recording performative utterances. The style, structure, and content meet the requirements for scientific papers and the guidelines of the publication in which the author intends to publish the article. The style is academic, but accessible to lawyers and philosophers. The clarity of the presentation compensates for the complexity of the topic. The structure of the article is logical, it traces the presentation of the material from the theoretical foundations to practical examples. However, the lack of subtitles makes navigation more difficult. The content is deep, based on primary sources (Hart, Austin, Wittgenstein) and modern research. Examples from judicial practice strengthen the argument. The list of references is extensive and includes classical works on the philosophy of language (Wittgenstein, Austin), modern research on the analytical philosophy of law (Hart, Ogleznev), procedural codes and commentaries to them. The author indirectly polemizes with supporters of a formal dogmatic approach that ignores the linguistic aspects of law. He also enters into a correspondence discussion with critics of "non-descriptive" concepts that deny their significance for legal practice. However, along with these polemics, the text lacks, in the reviewer's opinion, a direct discussion with those researchers who consider speech acts secondary to procedural law. Nevertheless, the author's conclusions about speech acts (as key tools for the formation of procedural facts), judicial communication (in terms of strict observance of context, sincerity and form), audio protocols (in their critical role in fixing performative statements), are of unequivocal interest to the readership. The article will be useful to scientists (lawyers, philosophers) to deepen the theories of law and language, to law enforcement officers to improve judicial speech skills, as well as to students as a guide for interdisciplinary research. Conclusion: the article is of significant scientific and practical value, opening up new perspectives for language learning in law and can be recommended for publication in a selected journal.

Third Peer Review

Peer reviewers' evaluations remain confidential and are not disclosed to the public. Only external reviews, authorized for publication by the article's author(s), are made public. Typically, these final reviews are conducted after the manuscript's revision. Adhering to our double-blind review policy, the reviewer's identity is kept confidential.
The list of publisher reviewers can be found here.

The subject of the research in the reviewed article is the application of the methods of analytical philosophy of language to the analysis of communicative processes occurring within the framework of the civil process. The author explores how the speech acts of the participants in the trial acquire the status of procedural legal facts and form the dynamics of the judicial process. Special attention is paid to performative statements and their role in creating procedural reality. The author uses an interdisciplinary approach combining the methods of analytical philosophy of law, linguistic analysis and legal dogmatics. The concepts of speech acts by J. R.R. Tolkien are used as a methodological basis. Austin, J. Searle and the legal philosophy of G.L.A. Hart, as well as the works of L. Wittgenstein. The author himself characterizes his methodology as "intuitively scientific", which indicates a certain degree of heuristic approach. The research is based on an analysis of regulatory acts (CPC RF, APC RF), court records, as well as theoretical constructions of the philosophy of language. Relevance The relevance of the study is due to several factors: There is a growing interest in the communicative theory of law and the application of analytical philosophy methods in jurisprudence. Digitalization of legal proceedings and new ways of recording the judicial process (audio recording), which expand the possibilities of analyzing speech acts in the judicial process. Insufficient theoretical elaboration of the connection between procedural legal facts and speech acts in the civil process. It is of practical importance for judicial lawyers to understand the mechanisms of the influence of speech acts on the course of judicial proceedings. Scientific novelty The scientific novelty of the research consists in the following aspects: The author for the first time applies the theory of speech acts to the analysis of procedural legal facts in the civil process, revealing their communicative nature. The classification of speech acts used in civil and arbitration proceedings is proposed, based on the typology of J. P. Blavatsky. Austin and J. Searle. The author analyzes the specific conditions for the success of performative statements in the judicial process (context, sincerity, authority, irrevocability). The connection between descriptive and ascriptive concepts in law (according to the classification of G.L.A. Hart) and their functioning in the civil process is revealed. The thesis of the "secondary nature" of law in relation to the variability of events is substantiated and the mechanism of transformation of potential variability into judicial reality through speech acts is shown. The style, structure, and content of the article correspond to scientific discourse, but are characterized by a certain metaphor and imagery, which is justified by the interdisciplinary nature of the research. The author uses both special legal terminology and the conceptual framework of the philosophy of language, providing their explanation. The structure of the work is generally logical, although there is not always a clear sequence of presentation. The article begins with an appeal to the principles of oral and written language in the civil process, then the concepts of procedural legal facts are introduced, then the author proceeds to the theory of speech acts and concludes with an analysis of the specifics of performative statements in the judicial process. However, in some places there are logical gaps between the sections, making it difficult to perceive the overall concept. The content of the article demonstrates the author's deep understanding of both philosophical and linguistic concepts and procedural aspects of the civil process. The part about specific speech formulas and their procedural meaning is particularly valuable ("We file a motion to involve A as a co-respondent", "The court appoints an expert examination by its ruling", etc.). The author convincingly shows how these formulas acquire the status of procedural legal facts and influence the dynamics of the process. At the same time, the content of the paper could benefit from a more detailed consideration of practical examples demonstrating how specific speech acts change the course of judicial proceedings. The bibliography of the article is quite representative and includes both classical works on the analytical philosophy of language (L. Wittgenstein, J. Austin, J. Searle, G.L.A. Hart) and modern works by Russian jurists. The range of sources covers the period from 1958 to 2024, which indicates the relevance of the study. The list of references includes monographs, dissertation research, and scientific articles, which indicates the author's versatile approach to the study of the topic. A positive aspect is the availability of modern sources from 2022-2024, as well as works with assigned DOI and EDN indexes, which confirms their scientific significance. However, the bibliography could be supplemented by a wider range of foreign studies in recent years on the application of the theory of speech acts in legal practice. The author takes into account possible objections and alternative points of view to some extent, which is reflected in the discussion of various approaches to understanding procedural legal facts (the views of E.V. Vaskovsky, E.G. Lukyanov, P.F. Eliseikin). However, in general, the polemical aspect of the article is not sufficiently developed. The author could have formulated more clearly possible objections to the application of the theory of speech acts to the analysis of the judicial process and offered convincing counterarguments. For example, the criticism of performative theory from other areas of the philosophy of law or the possible limitations of the application of linguistic analysis to legal phenomena is not considered. In addition, insufficient attention has been paid to the relationship of the proposed approach with other theories of legal facts and procedural actions. Conclusions and interest of the readership The article is an original interdisciplinary study that touches on important aspects of the philosophy of law and civil procedure. The author offers an interesting approach to the analysis of procedural actions through the prism of the theory of speech acts, which allows for a new look at the nature of procedural legal facts. The advantages of the work include: Innovative application of analytical philosophy methods to the analysis of the civil process Convincing substantiation of the communicative nature of procedural legal facts Identification of the features of performative statements in the judicial process Practical orientation of conclusions relevant to judicial practice Main disadvantages of the study: Some vagueness of the structure and logic of presentation Insufficient number of specific practical examples Weak polemical component Lack of clear practical recommendations on the use of the identified patterns The article will present of interest to a wide readership, including: Legal theorists and philosophers interested in the problems of analytical philosophy of law, Specialists in the field of civil and arbitration process, Practicing lawyers seeking to deepen the understanding of the communicative aspects of the judicial process, law students studying the philosophy of law and civil procedure In general, despite the noted shortcomings, the article deserves publication in the journal "Philosophy and Culture" as an original study, contributing contribution to the development of the communicative theory of law and analytical jurisprudence in Russian scientific discourse.
We use cookies to make your experience of our websites better. By using and further navigating this website you accept this. Accept and Close